Expansion Internet en China-  ASIASPAIN
 

Google

 

| 酒店 | 机票 | 西班牙| 演出票 | 租车 | 马德里 | 餐馆 | 欧洲 | 去西班牙学语言 | 搜索 | Nuevo: Cruceros | Escapadas | Ciudades China

我们在亚洲与西班牙之间架起了数字桥梁 Comunidad hispano Asiatica - 中国人 在西班牙 - 飛行  - 西语 - 英语  - Espa駉l English

首页 | 西语论 坛 | 博客 | 西班牙文章 | 西班 牙新闻 | 音像 | 西班牙信息 | 商店 | 搜 索 | 贸易 | 交友 | 涂鸦板 | 西语角 | 西班牙 | 再见城市  | 语言学常识  - 登录 注册西班牙 - AsiaSpain - 亚西网 设为首页西班牙 - AsiaSpain - 亚西网 加入收藏西班牙AsiaSpain亚西网 咨 询邮箱西班牙AsiaSpain亚西网

Aventura| Hoteles | Pekin | Shanghai | Videos  | Guias | Viajes por Asia | Noticias Asia | Taoismo | Dao De Jing | Ciudades de Espa馻 | Mapa de Espa馻 | Semana Santa en Espa馻 | My Summer in Spain | My News | Directorio


Filosofia China

We link Asia & Spain

法学学派 科学学派  历史学派 经济学派 数学学派 哲学学派 学术学派 语言学派 宗教学派 教法学派 佛教学派 政治学派 建筑学派 管理学派 民族学学派

MING JIA - GONSUNGLONGZI - TAOISMO

百家
儒家 法家 墨家 道家 名家
杂家 农家 兵家 阴阳家 纵横家

"Technically, classical China had semantic theory but no logic. Western historians, confusing logic and theory of language, used the term `logicians' to describe those philosophers whom the Chinese called the 'name school'. The best known of these were Hui Shi (380-305 b. C.) and Gongsun Lung (b. 380 b. C.?). This group now also includes the Later Mohists and the term `distinction school' (translated as `dialecticians') has become common.
The importance of the more detailed Mohist work came to light in modern times. The Confucian tradition had lost access to it. Rescuing that text rekindled a long-lost interest in Chinese theories of language. The restored Mohist texts give us a general theory of how words work. A term picks out part of reality. Some terms are more general than others; terms like 'dobbin' or 'horse' or 'object' might pick out the same thing. When we use a term to pick something out, we commit ourselves to using the name to pick out similar things and 'stopping' with the dissimilar. Thus, for each term we learn an 'is this' and an 'is not'. 'Is not' generates an opposite for each name and marks the point of distinction or discrimination.
Chinese doctrine portrays disagreements as arising from different ways of making the distinctions that give rise to opposites. The word bian (distinction/dispute) thus came to stand for a philosophical dispute. The Mohists argued that, in a `distinction/dispute', one party will always be right. For any descriptive term, the thing in question will either be an 'is this' or an 'is not'. Mohists were realistic about descriptions and the world. Real similarities and differences underlie our language. They rejected the claim that words distort reality; to regard all language as 'perverse', they noted, was 'perverse'. The Mohists failed, however, to give a good account of what similarities and differences should count in making a distinction. Mohists also found that combining terms was semantically fickle. In the simplest case, the compound picked out the sum of what the individual terms did. Classical Chinese lacked pluralization so 'cat-dog' works like 'cats and dogs'. Other compound terms (such as 'white horse') worked as they do in English. The confusion led Gongsun Long to argue, on Confucian grounds, that we could say 'white horse is not horse'."

From: Chad Hansen - Logic in China - in: Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Craig Edward. London, New York: Routledge 1998 pp. pp. 694-695.

"Systematic argument in Chinese philosophy began with the Moist school, founded in the fifth century b. C. by the first anti-Confucian thinker Mo Tzu (c. 468 - c. 376 b. C.). He laid down three tests for the validity of a doctrine: ancient authority, common observation, and practical effect. At first the controversies of the various schools over moral and political principles led to increasing rigor in argument; then to an interest in dialectic for its own sake, as evidenced in Hui Shih's paradoxes of infinity and in Kung-sun Lung's sophism "A (white) horse is not a horse"; and still later to the antirationalism of the Taoist Chuang Tzu (born c. 369 B.C.), who rejected all dialectic on the grounds that names have only an arbitrary connection with objects and that any point of view is right for those who accept the choice of names it assumes.
Logic of Moism. In the third century B.C. the Moists responded to Chuang Tzu's skepticism by systematizing dialectic in the "Moist Canons" and the slightly later Ta-ch' and Hsiao-ch'.
"Moist Canons." The "Canons" confined dialectic to questions of the form "Is it this or is it not?" or, since they assumed that the proposition is merely a complex name for a complex object, "Is it or is it not the case that . . . ?" (The form is distinguished in Chinese by a verbless sentence with a final particle, not by a verb "to be.") In true dialectic the alternatives are paired ("Is it an ox or not?") so that one and only one fits the object. Dialectic excludes such questions as "Is it an ox or a horse?" (it may be neither) and "Is it a puppy or a dog?" (it may be both). Its solutions are absolutely right or wrong; being or not being "this," unlike being long or short, is not a matter of degree, since nothing is more "this" than this is. The Moists further argued that it is self-contradictory to deny or to affirm all propositions: the statement "All statements are mistaken" implies that it is itself mistaken, and one cannot "reject rejection" without refusing to reject one's own rejection.
Names are of, three types, distinguished by their relations to "objects," which are assumed to be particular. "Unrestricted" names (such as "thing") apply to every object. Names "of kinds" (such as "horse") apply to every object resembling the one in question. "Private" names (for example, the proper name "Tsang") apply to one object. Whether a name fits an object is decided by appeal to a "standard." There may be more than one standard for an object; for "circle" the standard may be a circle, one's mental picture of a circle, or a compass. Some standards fit without qualification: a circle has no straight lines. Some fit only partially: in deciding whether someone is a "black man" it is not enough to point out his black eyes and hair. The "Canons" began with 75 definitions, evidently offered as "standards," of moral, psychological, geometrical, and occasionally logical terms. An example of a definition of a logical term is "'All' is `none not so' " (supplemented in the Hsiao-ch' by " `Some' is `not all' "). The first of the series is "The `cause' is what is required for something to happen." ("Minor cause: with this it will not necessarily be so; without this it necessarily will not be so. Major cause: with this it will necessarily be so.") The "Canons" also distinguish the senses of 12 ambiguous terms. Thus, "same" is (1) identical ("two names for one object"), (2) belonging to one body, (3) together, and (4) of a kind ("the same in some respects").
"Ta-ch'" and "Hsiao-ch'." The Moist Ta-ch' further refined the classification of names. Names indicating "number and measure" cease to apply when their objects are reduced in size; when a white stone is broken up it
ceases to be "big," although it is still "white." Names indicating "residence and migration" do not apply when the population moves, as in the case of names of particular states ("Ch'i") or of kinds of administrative divisions ("country"). The claim that one knows X only if one knows that an object is X applies only to names indicating "shape and appearance" ("mountain," but not "Ch'i" or "county").
The Ta-ch', and still more the Hsiao-ch', also showed a shift of interest from the name to the sentence and to the deduction of one sentence from another. The Chinese never analyzed deductive forms, but the Moists noticed that the formal parallelism of sentences does not necessarily entitle us to infer from one in the same way as from another, and they developed a procedure for testing parallelism by the addition or substitution of words. For example, "Asking about a man's illness is asking about the man," but "Disliking the man's illness is not disliking the man"; "The ghost of a man is not a man," but "The ghost of my brother is my brother." In order to reconcile the execution of robbers with love for all men some Moists maintained that although a robber is a man, "killing robbers is not killing men." Enemies of Moism rejected this as sophistry, on the assumption that one can argue from "A robber is a man" to "Killing robbers is killing men," just as one can argue from "A white horse is a horse" to "Riding white horses is riding horses." The Hsiao-ch' replied that there are second and third sentence types of the same form, which do not allow such an inference-for example, "Her brother is a handsome man," but "Loving her brother is not loving a handsome man"; "Cockfights are not cocks," but "Having a taste for cockfights is having a taste for cocks." A four-stage procedure was used to establish that "A robber is a man" belongs to the second type:
(1) Illustrating the topic ("robber") with things ("brother," "boat") of which formally similar statements may be made.
(2) Matching parallel sentences about the illustrations and the topic-for instance, "Her brother is a handsome man, but loving her brother is not loving a handsome man"; "A boat is wood, but entering a boat is not entering [piercing?] wood"; "A robber is a man, but abounding in robbers is not abounding in men, nor is being without robbers being without men."
(3) Adducing supporting arguments for the last and most relevant parallels by expanding them and showing that the parallelism still holds: "Disliking the abundance of robbers is not disliking the abundance of men; wishing to be without robbers is not wishing to be without men."
(4) Inferring, defined as "using its [the topic's] similarity to what he [the person being argued with] accepts in order to propose what he does not accept": "Although a robber is a man, loving robbers is not loving men, not loving robbers is not not loving men, and killing robbers is not killing men."

From: Angus C. Graham - Chinese logic - (Third section of: Logic, History of) in: The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edwards Paul. New York: Macmillan 1967. Vol. IV pp. 523.524.
 

学派

学派
法学学派 科学学派 历史学派 经济学派 数学学派
哲学学派 学术学派 语言学派 宗教学派 教法学派
佛教学派 政治学派 建筑学派 管理学派 民族学学派

FILOSOFIA CHINA - Viajes

Journal of Chinese Philosophy

Journal of Chinese Philosophy - A selection of full text articles

GONG SUN LONG ZI

Chad Hansen's Chinese Philosophy Pages

Your Hotel 换

 

我们在亚洲与西班牙之间架起了数字桥梁 亚 西之网路 - 中国人 在欧洲 - 飛行  - 中文 - 英语

expansion internet en China y Asia

Beach Hotel   book   Cuba   Spain - Mallorca   Sun AsiaSpain Benidorm Cuba   Alicante

1999 - AsiaSpain.com - 我们在亚洲与西班牙之间架起了数字桥梁 Contacto & I Think Google Recuerda: la palabra Agua no quita la Sed.